Norton v. City of Springfield, No. 13-3581 (7th Cir. 2015)

Annotate this Case
Justia Opinion Summary

Springfield has an ordinance that prohibits panhandling in its “downtown historic district”—less than 2% of the city’s area, containing its principal shopping, entertainment, and governmental areas. The ordinance defines panhandling as an oral request for an immediate donation of money. Signs requesting money are allowed, as are oral pleas to send money later. Plaintiffs received citations for violating this ordinance and alleged that they will continue panhandling but fear liability. They unsuccessfully sought a preliminary injunction. The Seventh Circuit upheld the ordinance in 2014, but granted rehearing in light of the Supreme Court’s 2015 decision, Reed v. Gilbert, and reversed. The majority in Reed stated: “A law that is content based on its face is subject to strict scrutiny regardless of the government’s benign motive, content-neutral justification, or lack of ‘animus toward the ideas contained’ in the regulated speech” and “a speech regulation targeted at specific subject matter is content based even if it does not discriminate among viewpoints within that subject matter.” The Seventh Circuit opined that the majority opinion in Reed effectively abolishes any distinction between content regulation and subject-matter regulation.

This opinion or order relates to an opinion or order originally issued on September 25, 2014.

Download PDF
In the United States Court of Appeals For the Seventh Circuit ____________________ No. 13-­ 3581 DON NORTON and KAREN OTTERSON, Plaintiffs-­ Appellants, v. CITY OF SPRINGFIELD, ILLINOIS, et al., Defendants-­ Appellees. ____________________ On Petition for Rehearing ____________________ DECIDED AUGUST 7, 2015 ____________________ Before EASTERBROOK, MANION, and SYKES, Circuit Judges. EASTERBROOK, Circuit Judge. Our first decision in this ap-­ peal concluded that Springfield’s anti-­ panhandling ordi-­ nance does not draw lines based on the content of anyone’s speech. Because the litigants agreed that the ordinance’s va-­ lidity depends on this issue, we affirmed the district court’s decision. 768 F.3d 713 (7th Cir. 2014). We deferred considera-­ tion of the petition for rehearing until the Supreme Court decided Reed v. Gilbert, 135 S. Ct. 2218 (2015). Shortly after deciding Reed, the Court remanded Thayer v. Worcester, 755 2 No. 13-­ 3581 F.3d 60 (1st Cir. 2014), a panhandling-­ ordinance decision on which our first opinion had relied, for further consideration in light of Reed. 135 S. Ct. 2887 (2015). At our request, the parties filed supplemental memoranda discussing Reed. We now grant the petition for rehearing and apply Reed to Springfield’s ordinance. As our first opinion explained, §131.06 of Springfield’s Municipal Code prohibits panhandling in its “downtown historic district”—less than 2% of the City’s area but containing its principal shopping, entertainment, and governmental areas, including the Statehouse and many state-­ government buildings. The ordi-­ nance defines panhandling as an oral request for an immediate donation of money. Signs requesting money are allowed; so are oral pleas to send money later. Springfield evidently views signs and requests for deferred donations as less impositional than oral requests for money immediately, which some persons (es-­ pecially at night or when no one else is nearby) may find threat-­ ening. 768 F.3d at 714. Plaintiffs contend that the ordinance’s prin-­ cipal rule—barring oral requests for money now but not regulating requests for money later—is a form of content discrimination. The panel disagreed with that submission for several rea-­ sons. We observed that the ordinance does not interfere with the marketplace for ideas, that it does not practice viewpoint discrimination, and that the distinctions that plaintiffs call content discrimination appear to be efforts to make the ordi-­ nance less restrictive, which should be a mark in its favor. We summed up: “The Court has classified two kinds of reg-­ ulations as content-­ based. One is regulation that restricts speech because of the ideas it conveys. The other is regula-­ No. 13-­ 3581 3 tion that restricts speech because the government disap-­ proves of its message. It is hard to see an anti-­ panhandling ordinance as entailing either kind of discrimination.” 768 F.3d at 717 (citations omitted). We classified the ordinance as one regulating by subject matter rather than content or viewpoint. Reed understands content discrimination differently. It wrote that “regulation of speech is content based if a law applies to particular speech because of the topic discussed or the idea or message expressed.” 135 S. Ct. at 2227 (emphasis added). Springfield’s ordinance regulates “because of the topic discussed”. The Town of Gilbert, Arizona, justified its sign ordinance in part by contending, as Springfield also does, that the ordinance is neutral with respect to ideas and viewpoints. The majority in Reed found that insufficient: “A law that is content based on its face is subject to strict scruti-­ ny regardless of the government’s benign motive, content-­ neutral justification, or lack of ‘animus toward the ideas con-­ tained’ in the regulated speech.” 135 S. Ct. at 2228. It added: “a speech regulation targeted at specific subject matter is content based even if it does not discriminate among view-­ points within that subject matter.” Id. at 2230. Three Justices concurred only in the judgment in Reed. 135 S. Ct. at 2236–39 (Kagan, J., joined by Ginsburg & Breyer, JJ.). Like our original opinion in this case, these Justices thought that the absence of an effort to burden unpopular ideas implies the absence of content discrimination. But the majority held otherwise; that’s why these three Justices wrote separately. The majority opinion in Reed effectively abolishes any distinction between content regulation and subject-­ matter regulation. Any law distinguishing one kind 4 No. 13-­ 3581 of speech from another by reference to its meaning now re-­ quires a compelling justification. Our observation, 768 F.3d at 717, that Springfield has at-­ tempted to write a narrowly tailored ordinance now pertains to the justification stage of the analysis rather than the classi-­ fication stage. But Springfield has not contended that its or-­ dinance is justified, if it indeed represents content discrimi-­ nation. As we said at the outset, the parties have agreed that the ordinance stands or falls on the answer to the question whether it is a form of content discrimination. Reed requires a positive answer. The judgment of the district court is reversed, and the case is remanded for the entry of an injunction consistent with Reed and this opinion. No. 13-3581 5 MANION, Circuit Judge, concurring. I join the opinion of the court in full, but write separately to underscore the significance of the Supreme Court’s recent decision in Reed v. Town of Gilbert, which held that a speech regulation targeted at specific subject matter is content-based even if it does not discriminate among viewpoints within that subject matter. 135 S. Ct. 2218, 2230 (2015). Reed injected some much-needed clarity into First Amendment jurisprudence and, in doing so, should eliminate the confusion that followed from Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U.S. 781 (1989). While Ward is well-recognized as the Court’s seminal time, place, and manner First Amendment case, it also described a standard for contentneutrality that was in tension with the Court’s developing content-based regulation of speech doctrine. Reed resolved this uncertainty. Ward stated that “[t]he principal inquiry in determining content neutrality ... is whether the government has adopted a regulation of speech because of disagreement with the message it conveys.” 491 U.S. at 791. Over time, courts interpreted this statement to mean that it did not matter if a law regulated speakers based on what they said, so long as the regulation of speech was not imposed because of government disagreement with the message. Under this approach, if an ordinance was not viewpoint-based, then it was content-neutral. For example, a local government’s decision to eliminate religious speech or abortion-related speech was considered content-neutral because it was not viewpoint-based—as, for instance, a regulation prohibiting “Christian speech” or “pro-life speech” was and remains. Reed eliminates this distinction. 135 S. Ct. at 2227 (concluding that a speech regulation is content-based if it prohibits the topic discussed or the idea or message expressed); 6 No. 13-3581 ante at 3 (“Reed effectively abolishes any distinction between content regulation and subject-matter regulation.”). On this point, Reed overrules Ward. Reed saw what Ward missed—that topical censorship is still censorship. Rejecting the idea that the government may remove controversial speech from the marketplace of ideas by drafting a regulation to eliminate the topic, Reed now requires any regulation of speech implicating religion or abortion to be evaluated as content-based and subject to strict scrutiny, just like the aforementioned viewpoint-based restrictions covering more narrow contours of speech. 135 S. Ct. at 2228, 2230. Few regulations will survive this rigorous standard. Because the court has faithfully applied Reed to the City’s ordinance, I concur.

Some case metadata and case summaries were written with the help of AI, which can produce inaccuracies. You should read the full case before relying on it for legal research purposes.

This site is protected by reCAPTCHA and the Google Privacy Policy and Terms of Service apply.