United States v. Heineman, No. 13-4043 (10th Cir. 2014)

Annotate this Case
Justia Opinion Summary

Defendant Aaron Heineman was convicted after a bench trial on one count of sending an interstate threat. The district court found that in 2010 and 2011, Defendant sent three e-mails espousing white supremacist ideology to a professor at the University of Utah. The first two e-mails did not contain threats, but the third made the professor fear for his safety and the safety of his family. Defendant argued that his conviction violated the First Amendment because the court did not also find that he intended the recipient to feel threatened. Agreeing with Defendant, the Tenth Circuit reversed and remanded.

Download PDF
FILED United States Court of Appeals Tenth Circuit PUBLISH September 15, 2014 UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS TENTH CIRCUIT Elisabeth A. Shumaker Clerk of Court UNITED STATES OF AMERICA, Plaintiff - Appellee, v. No. 13-4043 AARON MICHAEL HEINEMAN, a/k/a Aaron Heineman, Defendant - Appellant. APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE DISTRICT OF UTAH (D.C. No. 2:11-CR-00432-DN-1) Benjamin McMurray, Assistant Federal Public Defender (Kathryn Nester, Federal Public Defender, with him on the briefs), District of Utah, Salt Lake City, Utah, for Defendant Appellant. Elizabethanne C. Stevens, Assistant United States Attorney (David B. Barlow, United States Attorney, with her on the brief), District of Utah, Salt Lake City, Utah, for Plaintiff - Appellee. Before HARTZ, BALDOCK, and BACHARACH, Circuit Judges. HARTZ, Circuit Judge. Defendant Aaron Heineman was convicted after a bench trial on one count of sending an interstate threat. See 18 U.S.C. § 875(c). The district court found that he knowingly sent an e-mail that caused the recipient to reasonably fear bodily harm. Defendant argues that his conviction violated the First Amendment because the court did not also find that he intended the recipient to feel threatened. We have jurisdiction under 28 U.S.C. § 1291. Agreeing with Defendant, we reverse and remand.1 I. BACKGROUND In 2010 and 2011 Defendant sent three e-mails espousing white supremacist ideology to a professor at the University of Utah. The first two e-mails did not contain threats, but the third made the professor fear for his safety and the safety of his family. Entitled Poem, Aplt. App., Vol. 1 at 89, it began by addressing the professor by his first name, and contained the following language: Come the time of the new revolution we will convene to detain you And slay you, by a bowie knife shoved up into the skull from your pig chin you choke, with blood flooding in your filthily treasonous throat! We put the noose ring around your neck and drag you as you choke and gasp 1 The concurrence suggests that because the issue we decide here is now before the United States Supreme Court, we should await that decision before resolving this case. We respectfully disagree. That decision may not be handed down until next June, and there is always the possibility that an unexpected problem with the case will cause the Supreme Court not to proceed with its review. True, Defendant is on probation and will not suffer as much in the interim as one who has been incarcerated. But probation is not an insignificant sanction, and Defendant may well be subject to various restrictions on his civil liberties as a result of his felony conviction. 2 The noose laid on the tree branch and the fate hath conferred justice for Treason You are a filthy traitor along the horde of anti-American and anti-Whitey comrades whose justice shall come to be delivered To fuck the traitors, for justice! fuck Mexico! fuck South America! Fuck your soul to Hell! Into the furnace pool of MexiShit as the filthily traitorous asshole and puta! Id. at 90. Law-enforcement officers traced the e-mail to Defendant through his e-mail address, which had the user name siegheil_neocon. Id. at 91. When officers contacted him in writing, he responded immediately, Is this about the email? Id. He was charged in the United States District Court for the District of Utah with one count of sending an interstate threat, in violation of 18 U.S.C. § 875(c). Before trial Defendant requested an instruction that the government must prove that the defendant intended the communication to be received as a threat. Id. at 18. He asserted that he has Asperger s Disorder, which impairs his ability to understand how others will receive the things he says and does. Aplt. Br. at 2. The district court declined the request. Defendant then moved to dismiss the charge, arguing that § 875(c) was facially unconstitutional if it did not require proof that the defendant intended to place the hearer in fear of bodily harm or death. Aplt. App., Vol. 1 at 28. After the court denied the motion, the parties agreed to a bench trial on stipulated facts so that Defendant could preserve his legal arguments. He renewed his objections at trial, and the court again rejected them. It found that the government had established that Defendant knowingly transmitted a communication containing a threat to injure the person of 3 another, id. at 91, and that the poem was a true threat because it would cause a reasonable person to conclude that the sender . . . intended to cause bodily injury, id. at 93. The court did not determine whether Defendant intended the professor to feel threatened. II. DISCUSSION Defendant was prosecuted under 18 U.S.C. § 875(c), which states in relevant part: Whoever transmits in interstate or foreign commerce any communication containing . . . any threat to injure the person of another, shall be fined under this title or imprisoned not more than five years, or both. The law in this circuit is settled, and the parties do not dispute, most of what must be proved to establish a violation of the statute. For example, the statement itself must be one that a reasonable person in the circumstances would understand as a declaration of intention, purpose, design, goal, or determination to inflict [bodily injury] on another. United States v. Viefhaus, 168 F.3d 392, 395 (10th Cir. 1999); see id. at 396; United States v. Dysart, 705 F.2d 1247, 1256 (10th Cir. 1983). And [i]t is not necessary to show that defendant intended to carry out the threat, although the threat must be a serious one, as distinguished from words as mere political argument, idle talk or jest. Viefhaus, 168 F.3d at 395 (internal quotation marks omitted). The issue on appeal is whether § 875(c) requires proof of an additional element that the defendant intended the recipient to feel threatened. The statutory language contains no mens rea requirement, but as a statute that criminalizes speech, it must be interpreted with the commands of the First Amendment clearly in mind. What is a threat 4 must be distinguished from what is constitutionally protected speech. Watts v. United States, 394 U.S. 705, 707 (1969) (per curiam). Thus, we will read into § 875(c) any scienter necessary to satisfy the demands of the First Amendment.2 We review 2 The concurrence suggests that we can avoid the constitutional question by construing the statute without reference to First Amendment requirements. We respectfully disagree. If we were writing on a clean slate, we would certainly want to try that approach first. In our view, however, circuit precedent forecloses that path. First, we read United States v.Viefhaus, 168 F.3d 392 (10th Cir. 1999), as adopting an objective standard for the meaning of true threat. The opinion defines the term without including any requirement that the speaker intend the recipient to feel threatened. See id. at 395 96. The discussion includes the following sentence in italics: The question is whether those who hear or read the threat reasonably consider that an actual threat has been made. Id. at 396 (emphasis omitted). The question is not whether the speaker viewed the statement as an actual threat. Moreover, we read United States v. Dysart, 705 F.2d 1247 (10th Cir. 1983), as explicitly rejecting the interpretation of true threat advanced by the concurrence. We wrote: Defendant Dysart claims that two errors afflict the jury instructions. First, he says the trial court erred in failing to charge that for conviction under § 871, it must be shown that Dysart intended the letter to be taken as a threat, even if he had no intention of carrying out the threat. Second, he contends the trial judge erred when he refused to give an instruction on the relevance of evidence of Dysart s mental condition to the issue of Dysart s ability to form the requisite intent. Neither contention is persuasive. Id. at 1255 56 (emphasis added). The concurrence suggests that the instruction in Dysart actually contained the requirement requested by the defendant in that case. It points to the sentence in the instruction stating: The term threat means an avowed present determination or intent to injure presently or in the future. Id. at 1256 (internal quotation marks omitted). But that sentence came after the sentence: The question is whether those who hear or read the threat reasonably consider that an actual threat has been made. Id. (internal quotation marks omitted). The avowed-present-determination language is explaining to the jury what it is that the listener must consider to have been communicated. That is, it is saying that the language uttered by the defendant must be reasonably considered as an avowed present determination or intent to injure presently or in the future. First, we define what it means for a statement to be an actual threat. Then we decide whether it is Continued . . . 5 questions of constitutional law de novo. ClearOne Commc ns, Inc. v. Bowers, 651 F.3d 1200, 1216 (10th Cir. 2011) (internal quotation marks omitted). Defendant contends that the Supreme Court s opinion in Virginia v. Black, 538 U.S. 343 (2003), compels us to adopt his position. But before we examine that opinion, we turn to, and reject, the claims of both parties that we are bound by circuit precedent to adopt their positions. The government points to four of our decisions. Two can be disposed of summarily. Viefhaus predated Black. Whatever it said, a circuit precedent cannot bind us to the extent that it is inconsistent with a later Supreme Court decision. See Currier v. Doran, 242 F.3d 905, 912 (10th Cir. 2001). And United States v. Wolff, 370 F. App x 888 (10th Cir. 2010), like all unpublished decisions of this court, is not binding precedent. See 10th Cir. R. 32.1(A). The government s third case, Nielander v. Board of County Commissioners, 582 F.3d 1155 (10th Cir. 2009), is a post-Black precedent, but it did not address the issue before us. After successfully defending a state criminal-threat charge, Nielander brought a First Amendment retaliation claim in federal court under 42 U.S.C. § 1983. See id. at 1162 63. The district court granted summary judgment against Nielander on the ground that his statements (the alleged threats) leading to the alleged retaliation were not protected by the Constitution. See id. at 1163. We affirmed. See id. at 1165 66. We the speaker or a reasonable observer who must view the language of the statement as having that meaning. Dysart and Viefhaus state Tenth Circuit law that it is the observer. 6 held that even if Nielander s statements were protected speech, the defendants were entitled to qualified immunity. See id. at 1166 69. Two of the defendants had merely provid[ed] the police with their account of events, and had not brought any charges against Nielander. Id. at 1166. As for the defendant police officer, we said that he was entitled to qualified immunity because the law was not clearly established that Nielander s statements were not true threats. See id. at 1167 69. Although we used a pre-Black definition of true threat that did not include an intent to instill fear, see id. at 1167, we did not consider whether such intent was required, and we fail to see how our ultimate decision would have been affected if we had included that requirement because the evidence would have supported a reasonable belief that Nielander had that intent. See Brecht v. Abrahamson, 507 U.S. 619, 631 (1993) ( [S]ince we have never squarely addressed the issue, and have at most assumed the [standard], we are free to address the issue on the merits. ). The fourth case relied on by the government is United States v. Teague, 443 F.3d 1310 (10th Cir. 2006). Teague was convicted of transmitting an interstate threat under 18 U.S.C. § 875(c) after he sent a series of threatening e-mails to his former divorce attorney. See id. at 1311 13. His defense at trial was that he had not intended a threat, but that his e-mails were meant instead to prod the attorney to take various actions, were meant humorously, or merely stated the biological truth that the attorney and his family were going to die. See id. at 1312 13. On appeal he argued that the jury should have been instructed that he must have intended that his former attorney feel threatened and 7 not just that he sent the e-mail with knowledge that a reasonable person would take the message as a threat. Id. at 1318. But Teague had not raised that argument in district court, so we reviewed only for plain error. See id. Accordingly, he needed to show that the requirement of his additional element was clear under current law. Id. at 1319 (internal quotation marks omitted). Yet he conceded (incorrectly, as we shall see) that the Supreme Court had not spoken on the issue, and he acknowledged that this circuit had no controlling precedent and that the other circuits were split. See id. We readily concluded that there was no plain error. See id. The parties briefs did not cite Black, nor did our opinion. Teague could hardly stand as this court s interpretation of Black. Defendant in turn relies on two of our decisions. One is United States v. Pinson, 542 F.3d 822 (10th Cir. 2008), which concerned a prosecution under 18 U.S.C. § 871(a) for threatening the life of the President. See id. at 826. Pinson complained that the jury was instructed that an element of the offense was that he understood and meant the words mailed as a threat. Id. at 832 (internal quotation marks omitted). By making his intent an element, argued Pinson, the prosecution was enabled to put on prejudicial evidence of his state of mind. See id. at 831. We affirmed the conviction. See id. at 827. Some language in the opinion certainly supports Defendant s argument. We said: The burden is on the prosecution to show that the defendant understood and meant his words as a threat, and not as a joke, warning, or hyperbolic political argument. But a threat violates the law even if the defendant had no actual intention, or even ability, to carry it out. . . . The proper question for the jury is whether the defendant meant his words as a threat and whether a reasonable person would so regard them. The instruction here conveyed at least the first element of that meaning. It does not imply that 8 the defendant must be shown to have intended to carry out the threat, but it does require that the defendant understood and meant his words to be a threat. Id. at 832 (footnote omitted). But the opinion does not bind us in this case. It concerned a prosecution under 18 U.S.C. § 871(a), which, in contrast to § 875(c), explicitly requires that the offense be committed knowingly and willfully ; and it did not purport to be stating a proposition of constitutional law. Pinson does not cite any authority (much less First Amendment decisions) for its language supporting Defendant, and it does not otherwise explain why (other than the statutory requirement) a defendant must mean his words to be a threat. The other case relied on by Defendant is United States v. Magleby, 420 F.3d 1136 (10th Cir. 2005). Magleby had filed a motion under 28 U.S.C. § 2255 to challenge his convictions of burning and conspiring to burn a cross, in violation of the civil rights of an interracial couple. See id. at 1138 39. The success of one of his arguments turned on whether his appellate counsel had been ineffective for failing to challenge instructions on the elements of his offenses. In the course of the opinion we paraphrased Black as saying that a threat must have been made with the intent of placing the victim in fear of bodily harm or death. An intent to threaten is enough. Id. at 1139 (citation and internal quotation marks omitted). But our ruling on Magleby s claim of ineffective assistance of appellate counsel hinged on the pre-Black law in effect at the time of his earlier appeal. See id. at 1140. Any statement in the opinion regarding the meaning of Black was irrelevant to the opinion and therefore dictum. [A] panel of this court . . . is not bound 9 by a prior panel s dicta. Thompson v. Weyerhaeuser Co., 582 F.3d 1125, 1129 (10th Cir. 2009) (brackets and internal quotation marks omitted). Thus, we are facing a question of first impression in this circuit: Does the First Amendment, as construed in Black, require the government to prove in any true-threat prosecution that the defendant intended the recipient to feel threatened? We conclude that it does. At issue in Black were three state-law convictions for cross burning (or attempted cross burning) with intent to intimidate. See Black, 538 U.S. at 348 51. On an open field on private property, defendant Black had led a Ku Klux Klan rally that ended with the participants setting flame to a large cross 300 yards or so from a road, where passersby and neighbors could see it. See id. at 348 49. In a separate incident, defendants Elliott and O Mara had driven a truck into the yard of an African-American family that had recently moved into the neighborhood, planted a cross 20 feet from the house, and set it on fire. Id. at 350. The three were convicted of violating a Virginia statute that provided: It shall be unlawful for any person or persons, with the intent of intimidating any person or group of persons, to burn, or cause to be burned, a cross on the property of another, a highway or other public place, and, Any such burning of a cross shall be prima facie evidence of an intent to intimidate a person or group of persons. Id. at 348 (internal quotation marks omitted). The Virginia Supreme Court held the statute facially unconstitutional for two reasons: (1) the statute selectively cho[se] only cross burning because of its distinctive 10 message, and was therefore a content-based distinction within the category of true threats, which was impermissible under R.A.V. v. City of St. Paul, 505 U.S. 377 (1992); and (2) the prima facie provision rendered it overbroad because the enhanced probability of prosecution under the statute chills the expression of protected speech. Black, 538 U.S. at 351 (brackets and internal quotation marks omitted). It did not decide whether the prima facie provision was severable. See id. at 363. The United States Supreme Court affirmed in part and reversed in part. We discuss the opinion at some length because, in our view, it has been misconstrued by some courts that we highly respect. Black devotes little attention to what is required for a threat to be a true threat not protected by the First Amendment, and its sentence defining true threat (which appears in the Court s resolution of the R.A.V. issue) is somewhat ambiguous. Nevertheless, a careful review of the opinions of the Justices makes clear that a true threat must be made with the intent to instill fear. To resolve the R.A.V. issue, the Court, in an opinion by Justice O Connor for herself and four other Justices, began by reiterating the fundamental protection of speech embodied in the First Amendment. The hallmark of the protection of free speech is to allow free trade in ideas even ideas that the overwhelming majority of people might find distasteful or discomforting. Id. at 358 (internal quotation marks omitted). But it also noted that the Amendment permits restrictions upon the content of speech in a few limited areas, which are of such slight social value as a step to truth that any benefit that may be derived from them is clearly outweighed by the social interest in order and 11 morality. Id. at 358 59 (internal quotation marks omitted). As examples of permissible content-based restrictions, it included incitement to imminent breach of the peace, fighting words, and true threats. Id. Critical to the resolution of our case, the Court then defined true threats, stating: True threats encompass those statements where the speaker means to communicate a serious expression of an intent to commit an act of unlawful violence to a particular individual or group of individuals. The speaker need not actually intend to carry out the threat. Rather, a prohibition on true threats protects individuals from the fear of violence and from the disruption that fear engenders, in addition to protecting people from the possibility that the threatened violence will occur. Intimidation in the constitutionally proscribable sense of the word is a type of true threat, where a speaker directs a threat to a person or group of persons with the intent of placing the victim in fear of bodily harm or death. Id. at 359 60 (emphasis added) (brackets, citations, and internal quotation marks omitted). Turning to the Virginia statute, the Court acknowledged that cross-burning is symbolic expression, and therefore governed by First Amendment principles. See id. at 360. And it further acknowledged that R.A.V. held that even when a statute bans speech within an unprotected category (such as true threats), it ordinarily cannot discriminate by targeting only a subset of speech within the category. See id. at 361 62. Thus, the ordinance in R.A.V. was invalidated because it banned certain symbolic conduct, including cross burning, when done with the knowledge that such conduct would arouse anger, alarm or resentment in others on the basis of race, color, creed, religion or gender, id. at 361 (internal quotation marks omitted), but it did not cover, for example, those 12 who wish to use fighting words in connection with other ideas to express hostility, for example, on the basis of political affiliation, union membership, or homosexuality, id. (brackets and internal quotation marks omitted). R.A.V. did not hold, however, that prohibiting only a subset of a proscribable area of speech is always barred by the First Amendment. Id. In particular, the First Amendment permits content discrimination based on the very reasons why the particular class of speech at issue is proscribable. Id. at 362 (ellipsis and internal quotation marks omitted). Thus, [t]he Federal Government can criminalize only those threats of violence that are directed against the President since the reasons why threats of violence are outside the First Amendment have special force when applied to the person of the President. Id. (ellipses and internal quotation marks omitted). (But the government cannot ban only those threats against the President that mention his policy on aid to inner cities. Id. (internal quotation marks omitted).) Accordingly, the Virginia statute s ban on cross burning carried out with intent to intimidate [was] fully consistent with the dictates of R.A.V. because burning a cross is a particularly virulent form of intimidation. Id. at 363. On the First Amendment overbreadth issue, there was no Court majority. Three Justices did not address the issue; they would have invalidated the Virginia statute under R.A.V. See Black, 538 U.S. at 380 87 (Souter, J.). Of the remaining six, four (in an opinion by Justice O Connor for those who formed the R.A.V.-issue majority except for Justice Scalia) would have held that the statute was rendered facially unconstitutional by the provision that any such burning of a cross shall be prima facie evidence of an intent 13 to intimidate a person or group of persons. Id. at 363 (brackets and internal quotation marks omitted) (O Connor, J.). In their view, the flaw was that the provision strip[ped] away the very reason why a State may ban cross burning with the intent to intimidate. Id. at 365. The plurality explained: The prima facie evidence provision permits a jury to convict in every crossburning case in which defendants exercise their constitutional right not to put on a defense. And even where a defendant like Black presents a defense, the prima facie evidence provision makes it more likely that the jury will find an intent to intimidate regardless of the particular facts of the case. The provision permits the Commonwealth to arrest, prosecute, and convict a person based solely on the fact of cross burning itself. Id. [T]he act of cross burning may mean that a person is engaging in constititutionally proscribable intimidation, it said, [b]ut that same act may mean only that the person is engaged in core political speech. Id. Thus, the prima facie provision ignore[d] all of the contextual factors that are necessary to decide whether a particular cross burning is intended to intimidate. Id. at 367. The First Amendment, concluded the plurality, does not permit such a shortcut. Id. Justice Scalia, who was a member of the Court majority on the R.A.V. issue, dissented from the plurality on overbreadth. He disagreed with the plurality s interpretation of the prima facie provision, contending that it permitted an inference of the requisite intent only if the defendant put on no rebuttal evidence. See id. at 368 71 (Scalia, J.). And he argued that (1) so construed, the statute was not unconstitutionally overbroad because it would be highly unlikely to lead to any convictions for constitutionally protected conduct; and (2) the plurality should not have assumed its own 14 construction of the prima facie provision but instead should have remanded to the Virginia Supreme Court for a definitive interpretation. See id. at 371 79. He agreed, however, with setting aside Black s conviction because the jury had been instructed that it could infer his intent from the act of cross-burning itself, so the jury may have ignored evidence showing no such intent. See id. at 379 80. Finally, Justice Thomas would have upheld the statute, saying that cross-burning is not expressive conduct and the prima facie provision established a permissible inference. See id. at 388 400. We read Black as establishing that a defendant can be constitutionally convicted of making a true threat only if the defendant intended the recipient of the threat to feel threatened. The majority of the Court said that [t]rue threats encompass those statements where the speaker means to communicate a serious expression of an intent to commit an act of unlawful violence to a particular individual or group of individuals. Id. at 359. When the Court says that the speaker must mean[] to communicate a serious expression of an intent, it is requiring more than a purpose to communicate just the threatening words. Id. It is requiring that the speaker want the recipient to believe that the speaker intends to act violently. The point is made again later in the same paragraph when the Court applies the definition to intimidation threats: Intimidation in the constitutionally proscribable sense of the word is a type of true threat, where a speaker directs a threat to a person or group of persons with the intent of placing the victim in fear of bodily harm or death. Id. at 360 (emphasis added). 15 Moreover, the plurality s overbreadth analysis is predicated on the understanding that the First Amendment requires the speaker to intend to place the recipient in fear. According to the plurality, at least one First Amendment flaw in the prima facie provision was that a jury could infer an intent to intimidate from the act of cross-burning itself. Id. at 363. The prima facie provision, wrote Justice O Connor, does not distinguish between a cross burning done with the purpose of creating anger or resentment and a cross burning done with the purpose of threatening or intimidating a victim. Id. at 366. But how could that be a First Amendment problem if the First Amendment is indifferent to whether the speaker had an intent to threaten? The First Amendment overbreadth doctrine does not say simply that laws restricting speech should not prohibit too much speech. It says that laws restricting speech should not prohibit too much speech that is protected by the First Amendment. True, Justice O Connor s overbreadth analysis was not adopted by a Court majority. But that portion of her opinion did not include an analysis of what the First Amendment requires to convict someone of a true threat. The plurality obviously assumed that the discussion of the R.A.V. issue had already established that an intent to threaten was required. The one Justice (Justice Scalia) who had departed from the rest of the R.A.V.-issue majority to dissent on overbreadth in no way challenged the underlying assumption by the plurality that the First Amendment required an intent to threaten. On the contrary, he agreed with the reversal of Black s conviction on the ground that the instruction at his trial based on the prima facie provision could have led the jury to 16 convict without considering evidence that he had no intent to intimidate. See id. at 379 801 (Scalia, J.). Thus, the overbreadth discussion confirms our reading of the definition of true threat in the discussion of the R.A.V. issue. We also note that Justice Souter s opinion for the R.A.V.-issue dissenters also seems to have assumed that intent to instill fear is an element of a true threat required by the First Amendment. In support of the view that the Virginia statute could not survive First Amendment scrutiny, the opinion pointed out that the prima facie provision could encourage juries to convict despite weak evidence of an intent to intimidate. See id. at 384 87 (Souter, J.). The Ninth Circuit has read Black as we do. See United States v. Bagdasarian, 652 F.3d 1113, 1116 18 (9th Cir. 2011); United States v. Cassel, 408 F.3d 622, 630 33 (9th Cir. 2005). It said that a natural reading of Black s definition of true threats embraces not only the requirement that the communication itself be intentional, but also the requirement that the speaker intend for his language to threaten the victim. Cassel, 408 F.3d at 631. We also find some support from the Seventh Circuit. In United States v. Parr, 545 F.3d 491, 500 (7th Cir. 2008), it wrote: It is possible that the Court was not attempting a comprehensive redefinition of true threats in Black; the plurality s discussion of threat doctrine was very brief. It is more likely, however, that an entirely objective definition is no longer tenable. Other circuits have declined to read Black as imposing a subjective-intent requirement. See United States v. Clemens, 738 F.3d 1, 9 12 (1st Cir. 2013) (on plainerror review); United States v. Elonis, 730 F.3d 321, 327 32 (3rd Cir. 2013), cert. 17 granted, 134 S. Ct. 2819 (2014); United States v. White, 670 F.3d 498, 506 12 (4th Cir. 2012); United States v. Jeffries, 692 F.3d 473, 477 81 (6th Cir. 2012), cert. denied, 134 S. Ct. 59 (2013); United States v. Nicklas, 713 F.3d 435, 438 40 (8th Cir. 2013); United States v. Martinez, 736 F.3d 981, 986 88 (11th Cir. 2013). But the reasons for their conclusions do not persuade us. We discuss the opinion in Jeffries, 692 F.3d 473, because it expresses the various reasons for rejecting our reading of Black. To begin with, the Sixth Circuit said that Black had no need to impose a subjective-intent requirement because the Virginia statute already required that intent. It wrote: [Black] merely applies it does not innovate the principle that what is a threat must be distinguished from what is constitutionally protected speech. It says nothing about imposing a subjective standard on other threatprohibiting statutes, and indeed had no occasion to do so: the Virginia law itself required subjective intent. The problem in Black thus did not turn on subjective versus objective standards for construing threats. It turned on overbreadth that the statute lacked any standard at all. The prima facie evidence provision failed to distinguish true threats from constitutionally protected speech because it ignored all of the contextual factors that are necessary to decide whether a particular cross burning is intended to intimidate, and allowed convictions based solely on the fact of cross burning itself. Jeffries, 692 F.3d at 479 80 (emphasis added) (brackets, citations, and internal quotation marks omitted); accord Clemens, 738 F.3d at 11; Martinez, 736 F.3d at 986 87; Nicklas, 713 F.3d at 439 40; see Elonis, 730 F.3d at 330. But we do not read the plurality s overbreadth analysis as Jeffries does. As described above, one of the predicates for the plurality s overbreadth ruling was the Court s view that a threat was 18 unprotected by the First Amendment only if the speaker intended to instill fear in the recipient. If the First Amendment does not require subjective intent, how could it invalidate the statute for allowing a jury to find subjective intent on improper or inadequate grounds? See Cassel, 408 F.3d at 631 (Black s overbreadth analysis made clear that intent to threaten [is] the sine qua non of a constitutionally punishable threat ); White, 670 F.3d at 523 (Floyd, J., dissenting) ( If the First Amendment did not impose a specific intent requirement, Virginia s statutory presumption was superfluous to the requirements of the Constitution, and thus incapable of being unconstitutional in the way that the majority understood it. (quoting Frederick Schauer, Intentions, Conventions, and the First Amendment: The Case of Cross-Burning, 55 Sup. Ct. Rev. 197, 217 (2003))). Why would the First Amendment care how a jury goes about finding an element that is a matter of indifference to the Amendment? We cannot read the plurality s overbreadth ruling as derived from a lack of standards simpliciter. Also, Jeffries did not read Black s definition of true threat to include subjective intent. It said that Black s language True threats encompass those statements where the speaker means to communicate a serious expression of an intent to commit an act of unlawful violence conveys only that a defendant means to communicate when she knowingly says the words. Jeffries, 692 F.3d at 480 (quoting Black, 538 U.S. at 359); accord Martinez, 736 F.3d at 987; Elonis, 730 F.3d at 329; White, 670 F.3d at 508 09. Perhaps. There is certainly some ambiguity in the language quoted from Black about what the speaker must intend. But the natural reading is that the speaker intends to 19 convey everything following the phrase means to communicate, see Cassel, 408 F.3d at 631; White, 670 F.3d at 522 (Floyd, J., dissenting), rather than just to convey words that someone else would interpret as a serious expression of an intent to commit an act of unlawful violence, Jeffries, 692 F.3d at 480. And later in the same paragraph of Black two sentences resolve any ambiguity. The sentence immediately after the quote is, The speaker need not actually intend to carry out the threat. Black, 538 U.S. at 359 60. The proposition that the speaker need not intend to carry out the threat is a helpful qualification if there is a requirement that the defendant intend the victim to feel threatened. See White, 670 F.3d at 522 (Floyd J., dissenting). But no such qualification is called for if the preceding sentence means that the only requisite mens rea is that the defendant knowingly says the words. Jeffries, 692 F.3d at 480. Once it is established that the sole requisite intent is to say the (threatening) words, no reasonable person (juror) would then need to be informed that the defendant need not intend to carry out the threat. If there is no requirement that the defendant intend the victim to feel threatened, it would be bizarre to argue that the defendant must still intend to carry out the threat. A later sentence in the paragraph is still more definitive about Black s meaning. It says, Intimidation in the constitutionally proscribable sense of the word is a type of true threat, where a speaker directs a threat to a person or group of persons with the intent of placing the victim in fear of bodily harm or death. Black, 538 U.S. at 360 (emphasis added). The Court was not referring to intimidation as defined by the Virginia statute or even as it might be defined by other statutes, but the meaning that is required by the First 20 Amendment. Jeffries did not dispute that this sentence means that intimidation cannot be proscribed unless the speaker utters the threatening words with the intent of placing the victim in fear of bodily harm or death. 692 F.3d at 480 (internal quotation marks omitted). Rather, it disposed of the sentence by saying that it only shows that intimidation is one type of true threat, a reality that does little to inform § 875(c), which prohibits all types of threats to injure a person. Id.; accord Elonis, 730 F.3d at 329 n.4 ( [T]his sentence explains when intimidation can be a true threat, and does not define when threatening language is a true threat. ); Martinez, 736 F.3d at 987 ( [T]he general class of true threats does not require such an inquiry . . . . After all, intimidation is but one type of true threat . . . . [E]xplicitly requiring subjective intent for one discrete type of true threat makes little sense if the Court intended all true threats to require such intent. ). Yet why should the First Amendment require a subjective intent for intimidation but not other true threats? See White, 670 F.3d at 522 (Floyd, J., dissenting). Nothing in Black so much as hints at a reason for such a distinction. What is it about nonintimidation threats that makes them so much worse than threats of bodily harm or death that the First Amendment allows them to be prosecuted even when the speaker did not intend to instill fear? One would have thought the opposite that there should be less First Amendment protection for threats of bodily harm or death. The sentence in Black about intimidation is best read as merely applying the propositions stated earlier in the paragraph to the specific statute before the Court. 21 Jeffries found further support for an objective standard in the rationale for denying First Amendment protection to true threats: While the First Amendment generally permits individuals to say what they wish, it allows government to protect[ ] individuals from the effects of some words from the fear of violence, from the disruption that fear engenders, and from the possibility that the threatened violence will occur. R.A.V., 505 U.S. at 377, 388; Black, 538 U.S. at 344. What is excluded from First Amendment protection threats rooted in their effect on the listener works well with a test that focuses not on the intent of the speaker but on the effect on a reasonable listener of the speech. 692 F.3d at 480 (citations modified); accord Martinez, 736 F.3d at 987 88; Elonis, 730 F.3d at 329 30. Well said. But to say that the effect on the listener supports a threat exception to the freedom of speech does not mean that no other considerations come into play. For example, it may be worth protecting speech that creates fear when the speaker intends only to convey a political message. As we understand Black, the Supreme Court has said as much. When the speaker does not intend to instill fear, concern for the effect on the listener must yield. In short, despite arguments to the contrary, we adhere to the view that Black required the district court in this case to find that Defendant intended to instill fear before it could convict him of violating 18 U.S.C. § 875(c).3 3 Of course, as stated by the First Circuit, [I]t is rare that a jury would find that a reasonable speaker would have intended a threat under the particular facts of a case but that a competent defendant did not. Blum v. Holder, 744 F.3d 790, 802 n.17 (1st Cir. 2014) (internal quotation marks omitted). 22 III. CONCLUSION We REVERSE Defendant s conviction and REMAND for the district court to determine whether he intended his e-mail to be threatening. 23 United States v. Heineman, No. 13-4043 BALDOCK, J., concurring in the judgment only. The interstate transmission of any communication containing . . . any threat to injure the person of another is a federal crime. 18 U.S.C. § 875(c). The question presented in this case is whether § 875(c) requires the Government to prove a defendant s subjective intent to threaten. The court concludes the First Amendment requires such proof. But to my mind we should resolve this case without resorting to the First Amendment by simply construing the statute s text. Indeed, we are duty bound not to reach constitutional questions unnecessarily even if the parties ask us to do so. See Ulster Cnty. Court v. Allen, 442 U.S. 140, 154 (1979) (recognizing federal courts have a strong duty to avoid constitutional issues that need not be resolved ). Accordingly, I respectfully decline to join the court s opinion. I. In Clark v. Martinez, 543 U.S. 371 (2005), the Supreme Court explained that when deciding which of two plausible statutory constructions to adopt, a court must consider the necessary consequences of its choice. If one of them would raise a multitude of constitutional problems, the other should prevail. Id. at 380 81. This is the canon of constitutional avoidance. The canon is a tool for choosing between competing plausible interpretations of a statutory text, resting on the reasonable presumption that Congress did not intend the alternative which raises serious constitutional doubts. Id. at 381. Importantly, however, [t]he canon of constitutional avoidance comes into play only when, after the application of ordinary textual analysis, the statute is found to be susceptible of more than one construction. Id. at 385 (emphasis added). Therein lies the fundamental problem with this court s opinion. The court undertakes no ordinary textual analysis of § 875(c), but simply states [t]he statutory language contains no mens rea requirement and proceeds to engage the Constitution from the outset. Court s Op. at 4. After telling us it will read into § 875(c) any scienter necessary to satisfy the demands of the First Amendment, the court identifies the only question before us as whether the First Amendment . . . requires the government to prove in any true-threat prosecution that the defendant intended the recipient to feel threatened. Id. at 5, 10. The court undoubtedly applies the canon of constitutional avoidance prematurely, and perhaps unnecessarily. The Supreme Court s recent grant of the petition for a writ of certiorari in United States v. Elonis, 730 F.3d 321 (3d Cir. 2013), cert. granted, 134 S. Ct. 2819 (2014), is telling. The only question raised in the petition (the same question this court insists on answering) is [w]hether, consistent with the First Amendment . . . , conviction of threatening another person [in violation of 18 U.S.C. § 875(c)] requires proof of the defendant s subjective intent to threaten . . . ; or whether it is enough to show that a reasonable person would regard the statement as threatening . . . . Petition for a Writ of Cert., Elonis, 2014 WL 645438 (No. 13-983) (2014). Importantly, however, in its order granting the petition, the Court directed the parties to brief and argue an additional question: Whether, as a matter of statutory interpretation, conviction of threatening another person under 18 U.S.C. § 875(c) requires proof of the defendant s subjective intent to threaten. Elonis, 134 S. Ct. at 2819. The Supreme Court s order granting the petition in Elonis reinforces what Clark teaches us, namely that in interpreting § 875(c) we must first ask what its text requires rather than what 2 the Constitution demands. One need not be an oracle to understand what the Supreme Court first wants to know. And what the Supreme Court wants we should endeavor to provide.1 II. This court says in footnote 2 of its opinion that two circuit precedents, namely our decisions in United States v. Dysart, 705 F.2d 1247 (10th Cir. 1983), and United States v. Viefhaus, 168 F.3d 392, 395 96 (10th Cir. 1999), preclude us from deciding by way of ordinary textual analysis what sort of intent § 875(c) requires. Not so. We have never considered whether § 875(c) requires proof of a defendant s subjective intent to threaten. We have never even once held the term threat as used elsewhere in the criminal code excludes a defendant s subjective intent. Dysart involved a prosecution under 18 U.S.C. § 871, which proscribes threats against the President. To be sure, in Dysart the defendant argued the trial court erred in failing to charge that for conviction under § 871, it must be shown that [the defendant] intended the letter to be taken as a threat. Dysart, 705 F.2d at 1256. But a careful reading of Dysart 1 My initial response to the grant of certiorari in Elonis, given its nearly identical stature to this case, was to ponder whether we should decide this case now. Certainly, where a defendant is in custody, to delay a decision in favor of such defendant might be unfair notwithstanding a relevant grant of certiorari. But here, Defendant Heineman received a sentence of three years probation. Just last month, the district court reduced Defendant s sentence to two years probation. United States v. Heineman, No. 11-CR-432-DN, Corrected Order at 1 (D. Utah Aug. 8, 2014). Defendant has approximately six months left to serve. Today s judgment is no guarantee that Defendant will be free from state supervision anytime soon because the Government may choose to apply for certiorari or retry him. I see little need of rendering an opinion here when the Supreme Court had granted certiorari in another case that in all likelihood will resolve the matter before us. But because this court forces my hand, I too shall play my cards for better or worse. 3 reveals we never held otherwise. Instead, we explained that § 871 requires that the Government must prove a true threat , and the instructions given by the trial court met this requirement. Id. at 1256 (internal citation omitted). Those instructions, in addition to stating that the recipient must reasonably perceive the communication as threatening, elsewhere defined the term threat as an avowed present determination or intent to injure presently or in the future, and required the prosecution to establish a serious threat as distinguished from words as mere political argument, talk or jest. Id. The instructions also required consideration of the context in which [the words] were spoken, not the context in which they were heard. Id. (emphasis added). In short, the instructions which we approved in Dysart included a subjective intent component: that the speaker intend his threat be taken seriously, as opposed to in jest.2 In Viefhaus, by contrast, the defendant never argued 18 U.S.C. § 844(e), which proscribes bomb threats, requires proof of a defendant s subjective intent to threaten. Rather, the defendant argued his comments amounted only to vulgar political speech protected by the First Amendment. Viefhaus, 168 F.3d at 395. We rejected that argument by distinguishing a true threat from political speech based on its effect on the listener, much like the Supreme Court did in Watts v. United States, 394 U.S. 705 (1969). Importantly, 2 The court relies on Dysart s rejection of the defendant s subjective intent argument without ever acknowledging why we rejected that argument. We rejected that argument because the instructions as written already required proof of the defendant s subjective intent to threaten. Specifically, we rejected the contention that the instructions did not avoid the risk of conviction for a crude jest or expression of political hostility, because that contention is clearly untenable in light of the explicit guidance on that point found in the instructions. Dysart, 705 F.2d at 1256. 4 Viefhaus never addressed whether § 844(e) lacks a subjective intent component. In fact, our words suggest otherwise: A true threat means a serious threat as distinguished from words as mere political argument, idle talk or jest. United States v. Leaverton, 835 F.2d 254, 257 (10th Cir. 1987). We have previously defined threat by referencing the language of Black s Law Dictionary. See id. at 256 57. We again rely on that definition, but elaborate on the meaning of intent as it is used in that definition. Thus, we define threat as a declaration of intention, purpose, design, goal, or determination to inflict punishment, loss, or pain on another, or to injure another or his property by the commission of some unlawful act. See Black s Law Dictionary 1480 (6th ed. 1990); Webster s Third New Int l Dictionary (unabridged) 1176 (1993). It is not necessary to show that defendant intended to carry out the threat, nor is it necessary to prove he had the apparent ability to carry out the threat. The question is whether those who hear or read the threat reasonably consider that an actual threat has been made. It is the making of the threat and not the intention to carry out the threat that violates the law. Viefhaus, 168 F.3d at 395 96 (emphasis in original). Similar to the definition we approved in Dysart, our definition of a threat in Viefhaus implicitly contains a subjective intent component. The italicized statement appearing in the original cannot be read in isolation from the remainder of the text and, in particular, the sentences immediately preceding and succeeding it. Taken in context, that statement merely expresses our (correct) view that a defendant need not intend to carry out the threat or even have the apparent ability to do so. In no sense does the italicized statement suggest the Government need not prove a defendant s subjective intent to threaten as part of a § 844(e) prosecution. But regardless of how one chooses to read our precedents lest any doubt remain I am aware of no Supreme Court or Tenth Circuit decision that says a court s interpretation 5 of a term in one statute binds its interpretation of the same term in a different statute. In Hackwell v. United States, 491 F.3d 1229, 1235 (10th Cir. 2007), we explained that [w]hile there is no per se rule of statutory interpretation that identical words used in different statutes are intended to have the same meaning, we will nevertheless look at a statute s relationship to other statutes to determine Congress s intent. (internal quotations omitted). See also Envtl. Def. v. Duke Energy Corp., 549 U.S. 561, 574 (2007). What this means for present purposes is that any construction we may have given the word threat in a statute other than § 875(c) is merely one facet of a comprehensive textual analysis of § 875(c), not an excuse to forego such analysis altogether. Plainly then, Tenth Circuit precedent does not preclude us from undertaking a textual analysis of § 875(c) in the first instance. III. As noted in the court s opinion, a number of our sister circuits recently have addressed the meaning of § 875(c). See Court s Op. at 17 18. Oddly enough, however, Judge Sutton is the only circuit judge to date to address the question the Supreme Court now wants answered. In his separate dubitante opinion in Jeffries, Judge Sutton asks why the circuit courts have routinely construed § 875(c) through the prism of free-speech principles and, in particular, the Supreme Court s splintered decision in Virginia v. Black, 538 U.S. 343 (2003), without first simply construing its text.3 United States v. Jeffries, 692 F.3d 473, 485 3 Judge Sutton also authored the Sixth Circuit s opinion in Jeffries. Because the Sixth Circuit previously had held § 875(c) does not require proof of subjective intent, the court was required to address Jeffries argument that the First Amendment, via Black, invalidated all communicative-threat laws failing to do so. Jeffries, 692 F.3d at 483 (Sutton, J., dubitante). 6 (6th Cir. 2012) (Sutton, J., dubitante). The statute should require first what the words say . . . . Id. Only if our construction of § 875(c) s text raises constitutional concerns need we ask what constitutional avoidance principles require. Judge Sutton s dubitante opinion first addresses the wording of § 875(c), then its history, and finally background norms for construing criminal statutes. That is, he undertakes an ordinary textual analysis of § 875(c). Applying these conventional indicators of meaning, id., Judge Sutton comes to but one conclusion: In a case such as this, where everyone agrees the intent element of § 875(c) contains an objective component, see Watts, 394 U.S. at 708, courts need not rely on the First Amendment to interpret § 875(c) because the statute as written already requires the Government to prove a defendant s subjective intent to threaten. Courts relying on Black to construe § 875(c) have placed the cart before the horse. As to the meaning of the word threat itself, Judge Sutton points out Every relevant definition of the noun threat or the verb threaten, whether in existence when Congress passed the law (1932) or today, includes an intent component. To declare (usually conditionally) one s intention of inflicting injury upon a person, says one dictionary. 11 Oxford English Dictionary 352 (1st ed. 1933). An expression of an intention to inflict loss or harm on another by illegal means, esp. when effecting coercion or duress of the person threatened, says another. Webster s New Int l Dictionary 2633 (2d ed. 1955). A communicated intent to inflict harm or loss on another, says still another. Black s Law Dictionary 1489 (7th ed. 1999). And so on: An expression of intention to inflict pain, injury, evil, or punishment. American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language 1801 (4th ed. 2000). And on: An expression of intention to inflict something harmful. Webster s New College Dictionary 1149 (1995). And on: A declaration of an intention or determination to inflict punishment, injury, etc., in retaliation for, or conditionally upon, some action or course. Random House Unabridged Dictionary 1975 (2d ed. 1987). 7 *** If words matter, I am hardpressed to understand why these definitions do not resolve today s case. These definitions, all of them, show that subjective intent is part and parcel of the meaning of a communicated threat to injure another. Jeffries, 692 F.3d at 483 84 (Sutton, J., dubitante) (internal brackets omitted) (emphasis added). In other words, the dictionary definition of the word threat connotes subjective intent. One may cause another to feel threatened through an act of mere jest or even negligence (an objective inquiry), but one cannot threaten another without intending to do so (a subjective inquiry). Of course, Judge Sutton s definitional analysis is not immune from challenge. As Justice Frankfurter once commented: All our work . . . is a matter of semantics. 4 Notably, for instance, when defining a true threat in Black, the Supreme Court added language to the aforementioned dictionary definitions, perhaps to emphasize that subjective intent was part and parcel of that phrase.5 Compare Black s Law Dictionary 1489 (7th ed. 1999) 4 All our work, our whole life is a matter of semantics, because words are the tools with which we work, the materials out of which laws are made . . . . Everything depends on our understanding of them. William T. Coleman, Counsel for the Situation: Shaping the Law to Realize America s Promise 78 (2010) (quoting Justice Frankfurter). 5 In Black, the Court explained that the reasons why the First Amendment does not shield true threats is to protect individuals from the fear of violence and from the disruption that fear engenders, in addition to protecting people from the possibility that the threatened violence will occur. Black, 538 U.S. at 360 (quoting R.A.V. vs. City of St. Paul, 505 U.S. 375, 388 (1992)). The first two reasons lend themselves well to an objective intent standard that asks how a reasonable person would perceive the threat. The third reason, however, suggests the First Amendment may require the Government to prove subjective intent as part of any § 875(c) prosecution. If the culprit lacks a subjective intent to threaten, the possibility the threatened violence will occur seems at best rather remote. 8 (defining threat only as [a] communicated intent to inflict harm ), with Black, 538 U.S. at 359 (defining threat as where the speaker means to communicate a serious expression of an intent to commit an act of unlawful violence . . . . (emphasis added)). This arguably suggests dictionary definitions of a threat alone do not encompass the necessary subjective intent, or at least that the Supreme Court may not believe so. But, as Judge Sutton forcefully points out, any ambiguity in the dictionary definitions of threat is surely overcome by 1) the history of § 875, which from the beginning possessed a subjective intent component, originally, the intent to extort, and 2) the background norms for construing criminal statutes, which presume that intent [i.e. something more than negligence] is the required mens rea in criminal laws. Jeffries, 692 F.3d at 484 (Sutton, J., dubitante). Judge Sutton s analysis of the word threat as it appears in § 875(c) leads me to believe we too have placed the cart before the horse. At the very least, this court should tell us why Judge Sutton s view does not carry the day when the Supreme Court seems to think it might. 9

Some case metadata and case summaries were written with the help of AI, which can produce inaccuracies. You should read the full case before relying on it for legal research purposes.

This site is protected by reCAPTCHA and the Google Privacy Policy and Terms of Service apply.